| 0. Preface?
| xi
|
|
| 0.1 Welcome
|
|
|
| 0.2 What this book is not about
|
|
|
| 0.3 Coming attractions
|
|
Part 1: Scientific Explanations by Constraint
|
| 1. What Makes a Scientific Explanation Distinctively Mathematical?
| 3
|
|
| 1.1 Distinctively mathematical explanations in science as non-causal scientific explanations
| 3
|
|
| 1.2 Are distinctively mathematical explanations set apart by their failure to cite causes?
| 12
|
|
| 1.3 Mathematical explanations do not exploit causal powers
| 22
|
|
| 1.4 How these distinctively mathematical explanations work
| 25
|
|
| 1.5 Elaborating my account of distinctively mathematical explanations
| 32
|
|
| 1.6 Conclusion
| 44
|
|
|
|
|
| 2. "There Sweep Great General Principles Which All The Laws Seem To Follow"
| 46
|
|
| 2.1 The task: to unpack the title of this chapter
| 46
|
|
| 2.2 Constraints versus coincidences
| 49
|
|
| 2.3 Hybrid explanations
| 58
|
|
| 2.4 Other possible kinds of constraints besides conservation laws
| 64
|
|
| 2.5 Constraints as modally more exalted than the force laws they constrain
| 68
|
|
| 2.6 My account of the difference between constraints and coincidences
| 72
|
|
| 2.7 Accounts that rule out explanations by constraint
| 86
|
|
|
|
|
| 3. The Lorentz Transformations and the Structure of Explanations by Constraint
| 96
|
|
| 3.1 Transformation laws as constraints or coincidences
| 96
|
|
| 3.2 The Lorentz transformations given an explanation by constraint
| 100
|
|
| 3.3 Principle versus constructive theories
| 112
|
|
| 3.4 How this non-causal explanation comes in handy
| 123
|
|
| 3.5 How explanations by constraint work
| 128
|
|
| 3.6 Supplying information about the source of a constraint's necessity
| 136
|
|
| 3.7 What makes a constraint "explanatorily fundamental"?
| 141
|
|
| Appendix: A purely kinematical derivation of the Lorentz transformations
| 145
|
|
|
| 4. The Parallelogram of Forces and the Autonomy of Statics
| 150
|
|
| 4.1 A forgotten controversy in the foundations of classical physics
| 150
|
|
| 4.2 The dynamical explanation of the parallelogram of forces
| 154
|
|
| 4.3 Duchayla's statical explanation
| 159
|
|
| 4.4 Poisson's statical explanation
| 167
|
|
| 4.5 Statical explanation under some familiar accounts of natural law
| 173
|
|
| 4.6 My account of what is at stake
| 178
|
Part 2: Two Other Varieties of Non-Causal Explanation in Science
|
| 5. Really Statistical Explanations and Genetic Drift
| 189
|
|
| 5.1 Introduction to Part 2
| 189
|
|
| 5.2 RS (Really Statistical) explanations
| 190
|
|
| 5.3 Drift
| 196
|
|
|
|
|
| 6. Dimensional Explanations
| 204
|
|
| 6.1 A simple dimensional explanation
| 204
|
|
| 6.2 A more complicated dimensional explanation
| 209
|
|
| 6.3 Different features of a derivative law may receive different dimensional explanations
| 215
|
|
| 6.4 Dimensional homogeneity
| 219
|
|
| 6.5 Independence from some other quantities as part of a dimensional explanans
| 221
|
Part 3. Explanation in Mathematics
|
| 7. Aspects of Mathematical Explanation: Symmetry, Salience, and Simplicity
| 231
|
|
| 7.1 Introduction to proofs that explain why mathematical theorems holds
| 231
|
|
| 7.2 Zeitz's biased coin: A suggestive example of mathematical explanation
| 234
|
|
| 7.3 Explanation by symmetry
| 238
|
|
| 7.4 A theorem explained by a symmetry in the unit imaginary number
| 239
|
|
| 7.5 Geometric explanations that exploit symmetry
| 245
|
|
| 7.6 Generalizing the proposal
| 254
|
|
| 7.7 Conclusion
| 268
|
|
|
| 8. Mathematical Coincidences and Mathematical Explanations That Unify
| 276
|
|
| 8.1 What is a mathematical coincidence?
| 276
|
|
| 8.2 Can mathematical coincidence be understood without appealing to mathematical explanation?
| 283
|
|
| 8.3 A mathematical coincidence's components have no common proof
| 287
|
|
| 8.4 A shift of context may change a proof's explanatory power
| 298
|
|
| 8.5 Comparison to other proposals
| 304
|
|
| 8.6 Conclusion
| 311
|
|
|
| 9 Desargues' Theorem as a Case Study of Mathematical Explanation, Existence, and Natural Properties
| 314
|
|
| 9.1 Introduction
| 314
|
|
| 9.2 Three proofs - but only one explanation - of Desargues' theorem in two-dimensional Euclidean geometry
| 315
|
|
| 9.3 Why Desargues' theorem in two-dimensional Euclidean geometry is explained by an exit to the third dimension
| 323
|
|
| 9.4 Desargues' theorem in projective geometry: unification and existence in mathematics
| 327
|
|
| 9.5 Desargues' theorem in projective geometry: explanation and natural properties in mathematics
| 335
|
|
| 9.6 Explanation by subsumption under a theorem
| 341
|
|
| 9.7 Conclusion
| 345
|
Part 4: Explanations in Mathematics and Non-Causal Scientific Explanations -- Together
|
| 10 Mathematical Coincidence and Scientific Explanation
| 349
|
|
| 10.1 Physical coincidences that are no mathematical coincidence
| 349
|
|
| 10.2 Explanations from common mathematical form
| 350
|
|
| 10.3 Explanations from common dimensional architecture
| 361
|
|
| 10.4 Targeting new explananda
| 368
|
|
|
|
|
| 11 What Makes Some Reducible Physical Properties Explanatory?
| 371
|
|
| 11.1 Some Reducible Properties Are Natural
| 371
|
|
| 11.2 Centers of mass and reduced mass
| 378
|
|
| 11.3 Reducible properties on Strevens's account of scientific explanation
| 381
|
|
| 11.4 Dimensionless quantities as explanatorily powerful reducible properties
| 384
|
|
| 11.5 My proposal
| 386
|
|
| 11.6 Conclusion: all varieties of explanation as species of the same genus
| 394
|
| Notes
| 401
|
| References
| 461
|
| Index
| 483
|